共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
>P>Summary. We provide a set of simple and intuitive set of axioms that allow for a direct and constructive proof of the Choquet Expected
Utility representation for decision making under uncertainty.
Received: October 29, 2002; revised version: November 13, 2002
RID="*"
ID="*" We thank Matthew Ryan for very useful comments and suggestions on related work and for encouraging us to write this
note.
Correspondence to: S. Grant 相似文献
2.
We show that range convexity of beliefs, a `technical' condition that appears naturally in axiomatizations of preferences
in a Savage-like framework, imposes some unexpected restrictions when modelling ambiguity averse preferences. That is, when
it is added to a mild condition, range convexity makes the preferences collapse to subjective expected utility as soon as
they satisfy structural conditions that are typically used to characterize ambiguity aversion.
Received: February 25, 2000; revised version: April 17, 2000 相似文献
3.
Summary. We show, in the Choquet expected utility model, that preference for diversification, that is, convex preferences, is equivalent
to a concave utility index and a convex capacity. We then introduce a weaker notion of diversification, namely “sure diversification.”
We show that this implies that the core of the capacity is non-empty. The converse holds under concavity of the utility index,
which is itself equivalent to the notion of comonotone diversification, that we introduce. In an Anscombe-Aumann setting,
preference for diversification is equivalent to convexity of the capacity and preference for sure diversification is equivalent
to non-empty core. In the expected utility model, all these notions of diversification are equivalent and are represented
by the concavity of the utility index.
Received: July 27, 1999; revised version: November 7, 2000 相似文献
4.
Jiankang Zhang 《Economic Theory》2002,20(1):159-181
Summary. Using the Savage set up, this paper provides a simple axiomatization of the Choquet Expected Utility model where the capacity
is an inner measure. Two attractive features of the model are its specificity and the transparency of its axioms. The key
axiom states that the decision-maker uses unambiguous acts to approximate ambiguous ones. In addition, the notion of ‘ambiguity’
is subjective and derived from preferences.
Received: March 23, 2000; revised version: April 24, 2001 相似文献
5.
John Quiggin 《Economic Theory》2003,22(3):607-611
Summary. In this paper, it is shown that, for a wide range of risk-averse generalized expected utility preferences, independent risks
are complementary, contrary to the results for expected utility preferences satisfying conditions such as proper and standard
risk aversion.
Received: August 10, 2001; revised version: June 18, 2002
RID="*"
ID="*"I thank Simon Grant and an anonymous referee for helpful comments and criticism. This research was supported by an Australian
Research Council Senior Fellowship and Australian Research Council Large Grant A79800678. 相似文献
6.
We axiomatize a subjective version of the recursive expected utility model. This development extends the seminal results of Kreps and Porteus (Econometrica 46:185–200 (1978)) to a subjective framework and provides foundations that are easy to relate to axioms familiar from timeless models of decision making under uncertainty. Our analysis also clarifies what is needed in going from a represention that applies within a single filtration to an across filtration representation.Part of this research was conducted when Ozdenoren visited MEDS in Fall 2003. We thank Tapas Kundu, Costis Skiadas, Jean-Marc Tallon and Tan Wang for helpful discussions and also thank audiences at Koc University, Northwestern University, the CERMSEM conference “ Mathematical Models in Decision Theory” at Universite Paris I, and the FUR XI conference on foundations and applications of utility, risk and decision theory 相似文献
7.
Marco LiCalzi 《Economic Theory》2000,16(2):489-502
Summary. The decision-theoretic literature has developed very few techniques to bound the expected utility of a random variable when
only simple statistics like its median or mode or mean are known. One reason for this lack of results is that we are missing
a convenient way to link probability theory and expected utility. This paper is written to demonstrate a general (and genuinely
probabilistic) technique to obtain upper and lower bounds for the expected utility of a lottery.
Received: December 14, 1999; revised version: March 8, 2000 相似文献
8.
Summary. A well-known result in the medical insurance literature is that zero co-insurance is never second-best for insurance contracts
subject to moral hazard. We replace the usual expected utility assumption with a version of the rank-dependent utility (RDU)
model that has greater experimental support. When consumers exhibit such preferences, we show that zero co-insurance may in
fact be optimal, especially for low-risk consumers. Indeed, it is even possible that the first-best and second-best contracts
are identical. In this case, there is no “market failure”, despite the informational asymmetry. We argue that these RDU results are in
better accord with the empirical evidence from US health insurance markets.
Received: February 26, 2001; revised version: October 4, 2002
RID="*"
ID="*"The authors would particularly like to thank Simon Grant, John Quiggin, Peter Wakker and an anonymous referee for valuable
comments and suggestions on earlier drafts. The paper has also benefitted from the input of seminar audiences at The Australian
National University, University of Auckland, University of Melbourne and University of Sydney. Ryan also gratefully acknowledges
the financial support of the ARC, through Grant number A000000055.
Correspondence to:R. Vaithianathan 相似文献
9.
Fabio Maccheroni 《Economic Theory》2002,19(4):823-831
Summary. Let be a continuous and convex weak order on the set of lotteries defined over a set Z of outcomes. Necessary and sufficient conditions are given to guarantee the existence of a set of utility functions defined on Z such that, for any lotteries p and q, The interpretation is simple: a conservative decision maker has an unclear evaluation of the different outcomes when facing lotteries. She then acts as if she were considering many expected utility evaluations and taking the worst one. Received: January 19, 2000; revised version: December 20, 2000 相似文献
10.
Paolo Ghirardato 《Economic Theory》2002,20(1):83-92
Summary. I present an axiomatization of subjective expected utility and Bayesian updating in a conditional decision problem. This
result improves our understanding of the Bayesian standard from two perspectives: 1) it uses a set of axioms which are weak
and intuitive; 2) it provides a formal proof to results on the relation between dynamic consistency, expected utility and
Bayesian updating which have never been explicitly proved in a fully subjective framework.
Received: December 1, 2000; revised version: February 26, 2001 相似文献
11.
Lars Tyge Nielsen 《Economic Theory》1999,14(2):285-296
Summary. Differentiability is a convenient property of von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions which is almost always imposed but
has not been translated into behavioral terms. In applications, expected utility is usually maximized subject to a constraint,
and the maximization is carried out by differentiating the utility function. This paper presents two sets of necessary and
sufficient conditions for a risk averse von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function to be differentiable. The first of them is
formulated in terms of the equivalent risk premia of small gambles. It says, in brief, that the equivalent risk premium is
of a smaller order of magnitude than the risk itself, as measured by the expectation of the absolute value of the risk. The
second set of necessary and sufficient conditions is formulated in terms of the probability premium of small lotteries. It
says, essentially, that the probability premium for small binary lotteries goes to zero as the size of the lottery goes to
zero.
Received: May 11, 1997; revised version: May 14, 1998 相似文献
12.
Endogenous technological change with leisure-dependent utility 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
Paul A. de Hek 《Economic Theory》1999,14(3):669-684
Summary. This paper investigates the effect of introducing leisure-dependent utility into two models of endogenous technological change. Due to the flexibility in the labour supply the dynamics of the models change significantly. It is shown that if agents attach enough value to leisure in comparison to consumption two balanced growth paths may exist. This implies that economies with the same preferences and the same technology may experience different long-run growth rates. Received: October 17, 1997; revised version: January 6, 1999 相似文献
13.
Summary. This paper studies monotone risk aversion, the aversion to monotone, mean-preserving increase in risk (Quiggin [21]), in the Rank Dependent Expected Utility (RDEU) model. This model replaces expected utility by another functional, characterized by two functions, a utility function u in conjunction with a probability-perception function f. Monotone mean-preserving increases in risk are closely related to the notion of comparative
dispersion introduced by Bickel and Lehmann [3,4] in Non-parametric Statistics. We present a characterization of the pairs (u,f) of monotone risk averse decision makers, based on an index of greediness
G
u
of the utility function u and an index of pessimism
P
f
of the probability perception function f: the decision maker is monotone risk averse if and only if
. The index of greediness (non-concavity) of u is the supremum of
taken over
. The index of pessimism of f is the infimum of
taken over 0 < v < 1. Thus,
, with G
u
= 1 iff u is concave. If
then
, i.e., f is majorized by the identity function. Since P
f
= 1 for Expected Utility maximizers,
forces u to be concave in this case; thus, the characterization of risk aversion as
is a direct generalization from EU to RDEU. A novel element is that concavity of u is not necessary. In fact, u must be concave only if P
f
= 1.Received: 10 April 2001, Revised: 18 November 2003, JEL Classification Numbers:
D81.
Correspondence to: Michéle CohenAlain Chateauneuf, Michéle Cohen, Isaac Meilijson: We are most grateful to Mark Machina, Peter Wakker and two anonymous referees for very helpful suggestions and comments. 相似文献
14.
Lars Ehlers 《Economic Theory》2002,20(1):113-131
Summary. We consider the problem of allocating an infinitely divisible commodity among a group of agents with single-peaked preferences.
Thomson (1994a), S?nmez (1994), and Moulin (1999) introduce three different resource-monotonicity conditions. In each characterization they derive, the axioms are independent. Under Pareto-optimality, the three resource-monotonicity conditions are equivalent. We investigate whether the interchange of these conditions still yields a valid characterization,
and when the characterization still holds, whether it is a tight result or not. We strengthen each of the results, that is
either the used resource-monotonicity condition can be replaced by a weaker one, or by using another resource-monotonicity condition, the result is not tight. Our main result is that when at least three agents are present, the class of fixed-path
rationing methods is characterized by weak one-sided resource-monotonicity, strategy-proofness, and consistency.
Received: April 24, 2000; revised version: April 10, 2001 相似文献
15.
Emmanuel Thibault 《Economic Theory》2000,15(3):709-715
Summary. This note deals with the existence and uniqueness of a non-trivial steady-state equilibrium in an overlapping generations (OLG) model with productive capital and altruistic agents. We establish a necessary and sufficient condition for operative bequests which extends Abel (1987) and Weil (1987). Interestingly, we prove that the OLG model with production and altruistic agents always experiences a non-trivial steady-state equilibrium. Received: July 16, 1998; revised version: January 29, 1999 相似文献
16.
Alain Ayong Le Kama 《Economic Theory》2001,18(3):745-752
Summary. We extend the Beltratti, Chichilnisky and Heal's (1993) and (1998) continuous-time stochastic dynamic framework to analyze the optimal depletion of an asset whose consumption is irreversible, in the face of uncertainty about future preferences. Their model is rather general and so the results are general qualitative theorems. We show that in some interesting cases it is possible to solve their model analytically. The cases involve constant elasticity utility functions and the assumption of a Poisson process for the evolution of preferences. Received: September 13, 1999; revised version: November 23, 1999 相似文献
17.
Robert J. Aumann 《Economic Theory》2003,21(2-3):233-239
Summary. Evidence is adduced that the sages of the ancient Babylonian Talmud, as well as some of the medieval commentators thereon,
were well aware of sophisticated concepts of modern theories of risk-bearing.
Received: April 10, 2002; revised version: May 7, 2002
RID="*"
ID="*"Presented at the Institute for Mathematical Studies in the Social Sciences-Economics, Stanford University, August 4,
1981. Subsequent to that presentation, the author's attention was drawn to an article by Zvi Ilani, “Models in the Economics
of Uncertainty: The Cost of Concluding a Conditional Contract, according to the Talmud and the Halachic Literature,” Iyunim Bekalkala (Investigations in Economics), The Israel Association for Economics, Jerusalem, Nissan 5740 (April 1980), 246–261 (in Hebrew). Inter alia, Ilani treats
the Talmudic passage that forms the subject of this paper, and provides a fairly comprehensive review of the medieval commentaries
thereon; undoubtedly, he was the first to recognize in print the relevance of this passage to modern economic theories of
uncertainty. It is not clear, though, whether or not his understanding of the passage agrees with ours. The current paper
appeared in January 2002 in the Research Bulletin Series of the Research Center on Jewish Law and Economics, Department of
Economics, Bar Ilan University. 相似文献
18.
Choice under complete uncertainty: axiomatic characterizations of some decision rules 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Summary. We provide characterizations of four new rules for individual decision-making under complete uncertainty. They are what we
call the min-max rule, the max-min rule, the lexicographic min-max rule and the lexicographic max-min rule. These rules provide
orderings of the sets of possible outcomes associated with uncertain prospects. They provide significant alternatives to commonly-used
rules that focus on worst outcomes or best outcomes only, and lexicographic versions of those rules.
Received: August 20, 1998; revised version: November 3, 1999 相似文献
19.
Tito Pietra 《Economic Theory》2001,18(3):649-659
Summary. I consider the set of equilibria of two-period economies with S extrinsic states of nature in the second period and I assets
with linearly independent nominal payoffs. Asset prices are variable. If the number of agents is greater than (S-I), the payoff
matrix is in general position and S 2I, the set of equilibrium allocations generically (in utility function space) contains a smooth manifold of dimension (S-1).
Moreover, the map from states o
f nature to equilibrium allocations (restricted to this manifold) is one-to-one at each equilibrium.
Received: February 23, 1998; revised version: June 1, 2000 相似文献
20.
Hyun Park 《Economic Theory》2000,15(3):565-584
Summary. This paper demonstrates global stability of a competitive equilibrium in a multi-sector model of many firms, each of which
exhibits constant returns to scale technology, and of infinitely lived consumers, whose preferences are recursive but not
necessarily additively separable. In the topology induced by a sup-norm, the dominant diagonal blocks condition (Araujo and
Scheinkman (Econometrica 45, 1977)) allows us to apply the implicit function theorem to obtain continuity of the equilibrium path. If a stationary
equilibrium is locally asymptotically stable, then the continuity of the equilibrium path and smoothness of a weight function
on heterogeneous consumers imply that all equilibrium paths converge to the steady state. The dominant diagonal blocks condition
is also shown to be sufficient for the local asymptotic turnpike property.
Received: December 13, 1996; revised version: June 2, 1999 相似文献