共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 15 毫秒
1.
Leo Kaas 《Economic Theory》2001,17(2):307-323
Summary. It is known that overlapping generations models with imperfectly competitive firms may exhibit a continuum of stationary
equilibria. The reason of this indeterminacy is that different price expectation functions of consumers lead to different
objective demand functions against which firms maximize. All these expectation functions fulfill perfect foresight in the
equilibrium, but they can be arbitrary off the equilibrium. In this paper it is shown that it is not this arbitrariness which
is responsible for the indeterminacy, but that the continuum of stationary equilibria emerges even if expectation functions
are rational.
Received: March 25, 1999; revised version: February 16, 2000 相似文献
2.
A note on asymmetric and mixed strategy equilibria in the search-theoretic model of fiat money 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Randall Wright 《Economic Theory》1999,14(2):463-471
Summary. The simple search-theoretic model of fiat money has three symmetric Nash equilibria: all agents accept money with probability
1; all agents accept money with probability 0; and all agents accept money with probability y in (0,1). Here I construct an asymmetric pure strategy equilibrium, payoff-equivalent to the symmetric mixed strategy equilibrium,
where a fraction N in (0,1) of agents always accept money and 1-N never accept money. Counter to what has been conjectured previously, I find N > y. I also introduce evolutionary dynamics, and show that the economy converges to monetary exchange iff the initial proportion
of agents accepting money exceeds N.
Received: September 10, 1997; revised version: April 24, 1998 相似文献
3.
Yves Balasko 《Economic Theory》2003,21(1):1-18
Summary. In a two-period pure exchange economy with financial assets, a temporary financial equilibrium is an equilibrium of the current
spot and security markets given forecast functions of future prices and payoffs. The temporary equilibrium model can then
be interpreted as an Arrow-Debreu economy where preferences depend on prices. This identification implies, among other consequences,
the existence and the generic determinateness of the financial temporary equilibria associated with given forecast functions.
Received: December 29, 1999; revised version: December 20, 2001 相似文献
4.
Summary. For a number of reasons a large class of general equilibrium models from the field of resource economics does not allow for
an equilibrium analysis along the lines of the theory of infinite dimensional commodity spaces. The reasons concern the choice
of the commodity space and the applicability of properness assumptions with respect to preferences and the technology. This
paper illustrates the difficulties and shows for a prototype model how the problems can successfully be tackled by the use
of a limit argument on equilibria in the truncated economies.
Received: May 2, 1996; revised version: May 13, 1998 相似文献
5.
Klaus Nehring 《Economic Theory》2001,18(3):535-553
Summary. While the meaningfulness of the common prior assumption (CPA) under incomplete information has been established recently
by various authors, its epistemic rationale has not yet been adequately clarified. To do so, we provide a characterization
of the CPA in terms of a new condition called “Mutual Calibration”, and argue that it constitutes a more transparent and more
primitive formalization of the Harsanyi Doctrine than the existing characterizations. Our analysis unifies the understanding
of the CPA under incomplete information and clarifies the role of higher-order expectations and of the difference between
situations with only two and those with at least three agents. In the concluding section, the analysis is applied to the problem
of defining Bayesian consistency of the intertemporal beliefs of a single-agent with imperfect memory. The CPA yields a notion
of “Bayesian updating without a prior”.
Received: March 24, 2000; revised version: April 27, 2000 相似文献
6.
Summary. In a game with rational expectations, individuals simultaneously refine their information with the information revealed by
the strategies of other individuals. At a Nash equilibrium of a game with rational expectations, the information of individuals
is essentially symmetric: the same profile of strategies is also an equilibrium of a game with symmetric information; and
strategies are common knowledge. If each player has a veto act, which yields a minimum payoff that no other profile of strategies
attains, then the veto profile is the only Nash equilibrium, and it is is an equilibrium with rational expectations and essentially
symmetric information; which accounts for the impossibility of speculation.
Received: June 20, 2001; revised version: January 9, 2002
RID="*"
ID="*" We wish to thank Pierpaolo Battigalli, Fran?oise Forges, Franco Donzelli, Leonidas Koutsougeras, Aldo Rustichini, Rajiv
Vohra and Nicholas Yannelis for their comments.
Correspondence to: H. Polemarchakis 相似文献
7.
Summary. The paper constructs a theoretical framework in which the value of information in general equilibrium is determined by the
interaction of two opposing mechanisms: first, more information about future random events leads to better individual decisions
and, therefore, higher welfare. This is the ‘Blackwell effect’ where information has positive value. Second, more information
in advance of trading limits the risk sharing opportunities in the economy and, therefore, reduces welfare. This is the ‘Hirshleifer
effect’ where information has negative value. We demonstrate that in an economy with production information has positive value
if the information refers to non-tradable risks; hence, such information does not destroy the Blackwell theorem. Information
which refers to tradable risks may invalidate the Blackwell theorem if the consumers are highly risk averse. The critical
level of relative risk aversion beyond which the value of information becomes negative is less than 0.5.
Received: May 14, 2001; revised version: March 5, 2002 相似文献
8.
Moral hazard and general equilibrium in large economies 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Marcos B. Lisboa 《Economic Theory》2001,18(3):555-575
Summary. The paper analyzes a two period general equilibrium model with individual risk, aggregate uncertainty and moral hazard. There
is a large number of households, each facing two individual states of nature in the second period. These states differ solely
in the household's vector of initial endowments, which is strictly larger in the first state (good state) than in the second state (bad state). In the first period each household chooses a non-observable action. Higher levels of action give higher probability of the good state of nature to occur, but lower levels of utility. Households' utilities are assumed
to be separable in action and the aggregate uncertainty is independent of the individual risk. Insurance is supplied by a collection of firms who behave
strategically and maximize expected profits taking into account that each household's optimal choice of action is a function of the offered contract. The paper provides sufficient conditions for the existence of equilibrium and shows
that the appropriate versions of both welfare theorems hold.
Received: December 7, 1998; revised version: October 25, 1999 相似文献
9.
Nash equilibrium without mutual knowledge of rationality 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
Kin Chung Lo 《Economic Theory》1999,14(3):621-633
Summary. In a Nash equilibrium, players' rationality is mutual knowledge. However, both intuition and experimental evidence suggest
that players do not know for sure the rationality of opponents. This paper proposes a new equilibrium concept, cautious equilibrium, that generalizes Nash equilibrium in terms of preferences in two person strategic games. In a cautious equilibrium, players
do not necessarily know the rationality of opponents, but they view rationality as infinitely more likely than irrationality.
For suitable models of preference, cautious equilibrium predicts that a player might take a “cautious” strategy that is not
a best response in any Nash equilibrium.
Received: January 28, 1998; revised version October 2, 1998 相似文献
10.
Prabal Roy Chowdhury 《Economic Theory》2002,19(4):811-822
Summary. We consider a Bertrand duopoly model with increasing returns to scale where one of the firms have a cost advantage and prices
vary over a grid. We find that typically more than one equilibria exist. However, there are only two perfect equilibria. Moreover,
as the size of the grid becomes small, both these equilibria converge to the limit-pricing outcome.
Received: February 25, 2000; revised version: January 9, 2001 相似文献
11.
Felix Kubler 《Economic Theory》2001,18(1):73-96
Summary. There are a wide variety of theoretical general equilibrium models with incomplete security markets. In this paper we give
a general recipe for using homotopy algorithm to compute equilibria in these models. In many models, taxes, transaction-costs
or other market frictions introduce the additional difficulty that equilibrium prices or choices (but not equilibrium allocations)
may be undetermined. In order to demonstrate how these difficulties can be dealt with, we develop a globally convergent algorithm
to compute equilibria in a model with cash-in-advance constraints, several goods and incomplete financial markets. Furthermore
we describe how to implement the algorithm using a publicly available suite of subroutines for homotopy-pathfollowing.
Received: October 1, 1999; revised version: December 16, 2000 相似文献
12.
Summary. We provide a “computable counterexample” to the Arrow-Debreu competitive equilibrium existence theorem [2]. In particular,
we find an exchange economy in which all components are (Turing) computable, but in which no competitive equilibrium is computable.
This result can be interpreted as an impossibility result in both computability-bounded rationality (cf. Binmore [5], Richter
and Wong [35]) and computational economics (cf. Scarf [39]). To prove the theorem, we establish a “computable counterexample”
to Brouwer's Fixed Point Theorem (similar to Orevkov [32]) and a computable analogue of a characterization of excess demand
functions (cf. Mas-Colell [26], Geanakoplos [16], Wong [50]).
Received: September 9, 1997; revised version: December 17, 1997 相似文献
13.
Summary. Nearly all observational learning models assume that individuals can observe all the decisions that have previously been made. In reality, such perfect information is rarely available. To explore the difference between observational learning under perfect and imperfect information, this paper takes an experimental look at a situation in which individuals learn by observing the behavior of their immediate predecessors. Our experimental design uses the procedures of Çelen and Kariv [9] and is based on the theory of Çelen and Kariv [10]. We find that imitation is much less frequent when subjects have imperfect information, even less frequent than the theory predicts. Further, while we find strong evidence that under perfect information a form of generalized Bayesian behavior adequately explains behavior in the laboratory, under imperfect information behavior is not consistent even with this generalization of Bayesian behavior.Received: 29 January 2002, Revised: 12 May 2004, JEL Classification Numbers:
C92, D8.
Correspondence to: Boaçhan ÇelenWe completed most of this paper when we were both graduate students at New York University. This research was supported by the Center for Experimental Social Sciences (C.E.S.S.) and the C.V. Starr Center for Applied Economics at New York University. We are grateful to Andrew Schotter for his guidance and to an anonymous referee for his comments. We benefited from the expositional suggestions of William Baumol. We also acknowledge helpful discussions of Colin Camerer, Liran Einav, Xavier Gabaix, Douglas Gale, Charles Holt, David Laibson, and Matthew Rabin. We also benefited from suggestions by the participants of the 2002 International ESA Meeting and seminars at several universities. 相似文献
14.
Summary. The paper analyzes the properties of cores with differential information, as economies converge to complete information.
Two core concepts are investigated: the private core, in which agents' net trades are measurable with respect to agents' private
information, and the incentive compatible core, in which coalitions of agents are restricted to incentive compatible allocations.
Received: March 15, 2000; revised version: August 24, 2000 相似文献
15.
The Borda rule,Condorcet consistency and Condorcet stability 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Summary. The Borda rule is known to be the least vulnerable scoring rule to Condorcet inconsistency, Saari (2000). Such inconsistency
occurs when the Condorcet winner (the alternative which is preferred to any other alternative by a simple majority) is not
selected by the Borda rule. This note exposes the relationship between the Borda rule and the Condorcet q-majority principle as well as the Condorcet q-majority voting rule. The main result establishes that the Borda rule is Condorcet q-majority consistent when where k is the number of alternatives. The second result establishes that is the minimal degree of majority decisiveness corresponding to the Borda rule under sincere voting. The same majority is
required to ensure decisiveness under the Borda rule and to ensure that a q-rule (the generalized q-majority Condorcet rule) is a voting rule.
Received: April 8, 2002; revised version: July 17, 2002
Correspondence to:S. Nitzan 相似文献
16.
Summary. If the allocations of a differential information economy are defined as incentive compatible state-contingent lotteries over
consumption goods, competitive equilibrium allocations exist and belong to the (ex ante incentive) core. Furthermore, any
competitive equilibrium allocation can be viewed as an element of the core of the n-fold replicated economy, for every n.
The converse holds under the further assumption of independent private values but not in general, as shown by a counter-example.
Received: August 9, 1999; revised version: September 12, 1999 相似文献
17.
Summary. We study how currency restrictions and government transaction policies affect the values of fiat currencies in a two country,
divisible good, search model. We show that these policies can generate equilibria where both currencies circulate as medium
of exchange and where currency exchange occurs between citizens of different countries. Restrictions on the internal use of
foreign currency can cause the domestic currency to be relatively more valuable to domestic agents while taxes on domestic
currency create an incentive for home agents to hold foreign currency. We demonstrate that some policies increase prices and
lower welfare while others do the reverse.
Received: September 5, 2001; revised version: March 1, 2002 相似文献
18.
Indrajit Ray 《Economic Theory》2001,17(1):223-231
Summary. This paper compares the sets of Nash, coalition- proof Nash and strong Nash equilibrium payoffs of normal form games which
are closely related. We propose sufficient conditions for equivalent or closely related games to have identical sets of equilibrium payoffs.
Received: April 23, 1999; revised version: November 23, 1999 相似文献
19.
Elizabeth M. Caucutt 《Economic Theory》2001,17(1):25-51
Summary. In this paper, I develop an applied general equilibrium environment with peer group effects. The application I consider is
schooling. The framework used here is general equilibrium with clubs. I establish the existence of equilibrium for the economy
with a finite number of school types. This result is then extended to the case where the set of school types is a continuum.
The two welfare theorems are shown to hold for both economies. To compute the equilibrium, I construct a Negishi mapping from
the set of weights on individual type's utility to the set of transfers that support the corresponding Pareto allocations
as competitive equilibria with transfers. Because this mapping is a correspondence, a version of Scarf's algorithm is used
to find a competitive equilibrium.
Received: June 9, 1999; revised version: March 13, 2000 相似文献
20.
Summary. Recent experiments on mixed-strategy play in experimental games reject the hypothesis that subjects play a mixed strategy
even when that strategy is the unique Nash equilibrium prediction. However, in a three-person matching-pennies game played
with perfect monitoring and complete payoff information, we cannot reject the hypothesis that subjects play the mixed-strategy
Nash equilibrium. Given this support for mixed-strategy play, we then consider two qualitatively different learning theories
(sophisticated Bayesian and naive Bayesian) which predict that the amount of information given to subjects will determine
whether they can learn to play the predicted mixed strategies. We reject the hypothesis that subjects play the symmetric mixed-strategy
Nash equilibrium when they do not have complete payoff information. This finding suggests that players did not use sophisticated
Bayesian learning to reach the mixed-strategy Nash equilibrium.
Received: August 9, 1996; revised version: October 21, 1998 相似文献