共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 0 毫秒
1.
Jiankang Zhang 《Economic Theory》2002,20(1):159-181
Summary. Using the Savage set up, this paper provides a simple axiomatization of the Choquet Expected Utility model where the capacity
is an inner measure. Two attractive features of the model are its specificity and the transparency of its axioms. The key
axiom states that the decision-maker uses unambiguous acts to approximate ambiguous ones. In addition, the notion of ‘ambiguity’
is subjective and derived from preferences.
Received: March 23, 2000; revised version: April 24, 2001 相似文献
2.
Summary. We show, in the Choquet expected utility model, that preference for diversification, that is, convex preferences, is equivalent
to a concave utility index and a convex capacity. We then introduce a weaker notion of diversification, namely “sure diversification.”
We show that this implies that the core of the capacity is non-empty. The converse holds under concavity of the utility index,
which is itself equivalent to the notion of comonotone diversification, that we introduce. In an Anscombe-Aumann setting,
preference for diversification is equivalent to convexity of the capacity and preference for sure diversification is equivalent
to non-empty core. In the expected utility model, all these notions of diversification are equivalent and are represented
by the concavity of the utility index.
Received: July 27, 1999; revised version: November 7, 2000 相似文献
3.
Summary. We focus on the following uniqueness property of expected utility preferences: Agreement of two preferences on one interior indifference class implies their equality. We show that, besides expected utility preferences under (objective) risk, this uniqueness property holds for subjective expected utility preferences in Anscombe-Aumann's (partially subjective) and Savage's (fully subjective) settings, while it does not hold for subjective expected utility preferences in settings without rich state spaces. Indeed, when it holds the uniqueness property is even stronger than described above, as it needs only agreement on binary acts. The extension of the uniqueness property to the subjective case is possible because beliefs in the mentioned settings are shown to satisfy an analogous property: If two decision makers agree on a likelihood indifference class, they must have identical beliefs. Received: November 15, 1999; revised version: December 29, 1999 相似文献
4.
John Quiggin 《Economic Theory》2003,22(3):607-611
Summary. In this paper, it is shown that, for a wide range of risk-averse generalized expected utility preferences, independent risks
are complementary, contrary to the results for expected utility preferences satisfying conditions such as proper and standard
risk aversion.
Received: August 10, 2001; revised version: June 18, 2002
RID="*"
ID="*"I thank Simon Grant and an anonymous referee for helpful comments and criticism. This research was supported by an Australian
Research Council Senior Fellowship and Australian Research Council Large Grant A79800678. 相似文献
5.
Marco LiCalzi 《Economic Theory》2000,16(2):489-502
Summary. The decision-theoretic literature has developed very few techniques to bound the expected utility of a random variable when
only simple statistics like its median or mode or mean are known. One reason for this lack of results is that we are missing
a convenient way to link probability theory and expected utility. This paper is written to demonstrate a general (and genuinely
probabilistic) technique to obtain upper and lower bounds for the expected utility of a lottery.
Received: December 14, 1999; revised version: March 8, 2000 相似文献
6.
Summary. A well-known result in the medical insurance literature is that zero co-insurance is never second-best for insurance contracts
subject to moral hazard. We replace the usual expected utility assumption with a version of the rank-dependent utility (RDU)
model that has greater experimental support. When consumers exhibit such preferences, we show that zero co-insurance may in
fact be optimal, especially for low-risk consumers. Indeed, it is even possible that the first-best and second-best contracts
are identical. In this case, there is no “market failure”, despite the informational asymmetry. We argue that these RDU results are in
better accord with the empirical evidence from US health insurance markets.
Received: February 26, 2001; revised version: October 4, 2002
RID="*"
ID="*"The authors would particularly like to thank Simon Grant, John Quiggin, Peter Wakker and an anonymous referee for valuable
comments and suggestions on earlier drafts. The paper has also benefitted from the input of seminar audiences at The Australian
National University, University of Auckland, University of Melbourne and University of Sydney. Ryan also gratefully acknowledges
the financial support of the ARC, through Grant number A000000055.
Correspondence to:R. Vaithianathan 相似文献
7.
We show that range convexity of beliefs, a `technical' condition that appears naturally in axiomatizations of preferences
in a Savage-like framework, imposes some unexpected restrictions when modelling ambiguity averse preferences. That is, when
it is added to a mild condition, range convexity makes the preferences collapse to subjective expected utility as soon as
they satisfy structural conditions that are typically used to characterize ambiguity aversion.
Received: February 25, 2000; revised version: April 17, 2000 相似文献
8.
Koji Shimomura 《Economic Theory》1999,14(2):501-503
Summary. Based on some elementary results on duality, the paper proposes a much simpler way of deriving the class of non-homothetic CES production functions which was derived as a solution to a partial differential equation that defines the elasticity of substitution. Received: February 11, 1998; revised version: April 28, 1998 相似文献
9.
Fabio Maccheroni 《Economic Theory》2002,19(4):823-831
Summary. Let be a continuous and convex weak order on the set of lotteries defined over a set Z of outcomes. Necessary and sufficient conditions are given to guarantee the existence of a set of utility functions defined on Z such that, for any lotteries p and q, The interpretation is simple: a conservative decision maker has an unclear evaluation of the different outcomes when facing lotteries. She then acts as if she were considering many expected utility evaluations and taking the worst one. Received: January 19, 2000; revised version: December 20, 2000 相似文献
10.
Summary. Debreu proposed the notion of `least concave utility' as a way to disentangle risk attitudes from the certainty preferences embedded in a von-Neumann Morgenstern index. This paper studies preferences under uncertainty, as opposed to risk, and examines a corresponding decomposition of preference. The analysis is carried out within the Choquet expected utility model of preference and is centered on the notion of a least convex capacity. Received: May 7, 1997; revised version: November 5, 1997 相似文献
11.
Takashi Kamihigashi 《Economic Theory》2000,15(2):463-468
Summary. Ekeland and Scheinkman (1986) prove the necessity of a standard transversality condition under certain technical conditions. Their result is one of the most powerful on the necessity of a transversality condition currently available in the literature, and their proof involves numerous estimations and relies on Ekeland's variational principle and Fatou's lemma. This note relaxes some of their assumptions and provides a simple proof that uses neither Ekeland's principle nor a convergence result like Fatou's lemma. Received: April 24, 1998; revised version: September 8, 1998 相似文献
12.
Takashi Kamihigashi 《Economic Theory》2002,20(2):427-433
Summary. This note provides a simple proof of the necessity of the transversality condition for the differentiable reduced-form model.
The proof uses only an elementary perturbation argument without relying on dynamic programming. The proof makes it clear that,
contrary to common belief, the necessity of the transversality condition can be shown in a straightforward way.
Received: January 22, 2001; revised version: April 2, 2001 相似文献
13.
Lars Tyge Nielsen 《Economic Theory》1999,14(2):285-296
Summary. Differentiability is a convenient property of von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions which is almost always imposed but
has not been translated into behavioral terms. In applications, expected utility is usually maximized subject to a constraint,
and the maximization is carried out by differentiating the utility function. This paper presents two sets of necessary and
sufficient conditions for a risk averse von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function to be differentiable. The first of them is
formulated in terms of the equivalent risk premia of small gambles. It says, in brief, that the equivalent risk premium is
of a smaller order of magnitude than the risk itself, as measured by the expectation of the absolute value of the risk. The
second set of necessary and sufficient conditions is formulated in terms of the probability premium of small lotteries. It
says, essentially, that the probability premium for small binary lotteries goes to zero as the size of the lottery goes to
zero.
Received: May 11, 1997; revised version: May 14, 1998 相似文献
14.
Endogenous technological change with leisure-dependent utility 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
Paul A. de Hek 《Economic Theory》1999,14(3):669-684
Summary. This paper investigates the effect of introducing leisure-dependent utility into two models of endogenous technological change. Due to the flexibility in the labour supply the dynamics of the models change significantly. It is shown that if agents attach enough value to leisure in comparison to consumption two balanced growth paths may exist. This implies that economies with the same preferences and the same technology may experience different long-run growth rates. Received: October 17, 1997; revised version: January 6, 1999 相似文献
15.
Summary. We offer a new proof of the maximum principle, by using the envelope theorem that is frequently used in the standard microeconomic
theory.
Received: April 11, 2002; revised version: June 26, 2002
Correspondence to: K. Shimomura 相似文献
16.
Summary. This paper studies monotone risk aversion, the aversion to monotone, mean-preserving increase in risk (Quiggin [21]), in the Rank Dependent Expected Utility (RDEU) model. This model replaces expected utility by another functional, characterized by two functions, a utility function u in conjunction with a probability-perception function f. Monotone mean-preserving increases in risk are closely related to the notion of comparative
dispersion introduced by Bickel and Lehmann [3,4] in Non-parametric Statistics. We present a characterization of the pairs (u,f) of monotone risk averse decision makers, based on an index of greediness
G
u
of the utility function u and an index of pessimism
P
f
of the probability perception function f: the decision maker is monotone risk averse if and only if
. The index of greediness (non-concavity) of u is the supremum of
taken over
. The index of pessimism of f is the infimum of
taken over 0 < v < 1. Thus,
, with G
u
= 1 iff u is concave. If
then
, i.e., f is majorized by the identity function. Since P
f
= 1 for Expected Utility maximizers,
forces u to be concave in this case; thus, the characterization of risk aversion as
is a direct generalization from EU to RDEU. A novel element is that concavity of u is not necessary. In fact, u must be concave only if P
f
= 1.Received: 10 April 2001, Revised: 18 November 2003, JEL Classification Numbers:
D81.
Correspondence to: Michéle CohenAlain Chateauneuf, Michéle Cohen, Isaac Meilijson: We are most grateful to Mark Machina, Peter Wakker and two anonymous referees for very helpful suggestions and comments. 相似文献
17.
A simple example of complex dynamics 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Anjan Mukherji 《Economic Theory》1999,14(3):741-749
Summary. A discrete tatonnement process is analysed within the context of a two-person, two-good exchange economy where each person
has a Cobb-Douglas utility function. This process is shown to exhibit period doubling bifurcation, topological and ergodic
chaos.
Received: June 22, 1998; revised version: July 15, 1998 相似文献
18.
Uncertainty and entry deterrence 总被引:3,自引:0,他引:3
Eric S. Maskin 《Economic Theory》1999,14(2):429-437
Summary. We study a model where capacity installation by an incumbent firm serves to deter others from entering the industry. We argue that uncertainty about demand or costs forces the incumbent to choose a higher capacity level than it would under certainty. This higher level diminishes the attractiveness of deterrence (Proposition 1) and, therefore, the range of parameter values for which deterrence occurs (Proposition 2). Received: July 10, 1997; revised version: November 21, 1997 相似文献
19.
Ilaria Ossella 《Economic Theory》1999,14(3):597-607
Summary. This paper establishes a ‘turnpike theorem’ for a closed linear model of production with a primitive input requirement matrix. Optimal programs of resource allocation have a ‘turnpike property’ if the growth factor of every sector in the economy converges, in the long run, to a common value. The usefulness of such a theorem is due to the fact that the input requirement matrix for an economy with a large number of goods may be primitive (some power of the matrix is strictly positive). Received: April 19, 1998; revised version: July 15, 1998 相似文献
20.
Summary. We analyze a model of coalitional bidding in which coalitions form endogenously and compete with each other. Since the nature
of this competition influences the way in which agents organize themselves into coalitions, our main aim is to characterize
the equilibrium coalition structure and the resulting bids. We do so in a simple model in which the seller may have good reason
to allow joint bidding. In particular, we study a model in which the agents are budget constrained, and are allowed to form
coalitions to pool their finances before engaging in the first price auction. We show that if the budget constraint is very
severe, the equilibrium coalition structure consists of two coalitions, one slightly larger than the other; interestingly,
it is not the grand coalition. This equilibrium coalition structure is one which yields (approximately) the maximum expected
revenue. Thus the seller can induce the optimal (revenue maximizing) degree of cooperation among budget constrained buyers
simply by permitting them to collude.
Received: June 25, 1999; revised version: November 13, 2000 相似文献